This paper argues that even if the skeptical argument is sound, skepticism does not pose a serious challenge to our inquiry, for we can still make epistemic progress. The skeptical argument comes in various forms, all of which rest on a set of demanding criteria of knowledge. Suppose the skepticscriteria of knowledge are correct. Then if we can meet the criteria, then we may achieve knowledge; if we cannot meet this set of criteria, then we can merely acquire things that fall short of knowledge. Knowledge (given the skeptics criteria) is epistemically valuable. But things that fall short of knowledge may also be epistemically valuable. Consider two individuals, S1 and S2. Both believe the truth that there is a table in the room. But both are unable to rule out the possibility that each of them is a brain in vat. Yet there is a difference between S1 and S2. If there were a chair or stone instead of a table in the room, S1 would believe that there is no table in the room, while S2 would still believe that there is a table in the room. According to the skeptics criteria of knowledge, neither S1 nor S2 knows that there is a table in the room. Thus, if nothing that falls short of knowledge is of epistemic value, then ceteris paribus, S1 is not doing epistemically better than S2. But clearly, ceteris paribus, S1 is doing epistemically better than S2. Therefore, there is something (e.g., S1's cognitive state) that falls short of knowledge but is of epistemic value. In addition, the skeptical argument, even if it is sound, does not show that S1's cognitive state is unattainable. If S1s cognitive state is attainable and epistemically valuable, then we can make epistemic progress even if we cannot know anything about the external world given the skeptics criteria of knowledge. Historically, the skeptics argue not only that we cannot know anything, but also that we should suspend judgment. They seem to implicitly assume that one should believe p only if one knows that p, for from the fact that one does not know that p, it does not follow that one should not believe p. This assumption is known as the knowledge norm of belief. The knowledge norm of belief seems to presuppose that any cognitive state that falls short of knowledge is epistemically valueless. For if there is a cognitive state that falls short of knowledge but is epistemically valuable, then we do not have to suspend judgment when we cannot acquire knowledge. If we can acquire something of epistemic value by believing a certain proposition, we may believe it even if we do not know it. Thus, skepticism is false. Finally, this paper shows that contemporary responses to skepticism cannot avoid value talk. I discuss three kinds of responses: Mooreanism, abductivism, and contextualism. It is argues that each of them appeals to certain value assumptions. Specifically, the core idea of Mooreanism is that we can know p even if we cannot prove p or rule out all alternatives to p. This criterion of knowledge is less demanding than the skeptics criteria. A less demanding criterion of knowledge is plausible only if it does not entail that those who know that p are doing no epistemically better than those who merely believe that p (as far as whether p is true is not about a trivial matter). So Mooreans must assume that knowledge that p (according to their account of knowledge) is epistemically better than mere belief that p. In addition, both abductivism and contextualism employs the inference to the best explanation. Abductivism directly appeals to the inference to the best explanation. Contextualists argue that contextualism is better than alternative accounts of knowledge because contextualism best explains both why the skeptical argument is forceful and why the daily knowledge attribution is appropriate. What counts as the best explanation is clearly a value question.