Abstract:Against the background of debates over the meaning of names in the philosophy of language, Saul Kripke proposed a puzzle about names and beliefs in 1979. However, this puzzle, has in fact surpassed beliefs expressed using names. It extends even further to the broader concept of belief, which should be solved by any theory of belief attribution. In this paper, we propose a new solution to this puzzle.As a philosophical puzzle, Kripke’s puzzle about belief is derived from some premises. Kripke mentions the disquotational principle and the principle of translation. He further distinguishes between the simple disquotational principle and the strengthened disquotational principle. We argue that different conclusions can be derived from different versions of Kripke’s disquational principle, which in turn can distinguish between two different forms of contradictory beliefs: explicitly contradictory beliefs and implicitly contradictory beliefs. As humans, we are rational. Certainly, we should not have explicitly contradictory beliefs. Kripke’s Pierre shows that sometimes indeed we have implicit contradictory beliefs. This distinction needs to be drawn to show that holding implicitly contradictory beliefs is not in conflict with rationality.According to our distinction, normal rational people can reasonably have implicitly contradictory beliefs. If so, where do implicitly contradictory beliefs come from? We further argue that one’s intuition about the puzzle suggests that contradictory beliefs arise through the unfavorable emergence of empirical facts. Therefore, we think that Kripke’s puzzle about belief results from the occurrence of unfavorable empirical facts. If empirical facts favorably occur, i.e. if Pierre later moves to the downtown district of London, or if his impression of London when he was in France comes from some pictures of an unpleasant part of London, then there would be no puzzles. The generation mechanism of implicitly contradictory beliefs can be reasonably explained by introducing the concept of situation.Finally, this paper argues that by distinguishing between mental action and its products, a plausible explanation can be provided for how contradictory beliefs work, which is indicated by another intuition about the puzzle, i.e. direct language acquisition. In Kripke’s puzzle about belief, different language acquisition methods and experiences are essentially different mental actions that form beliefs. Pierre finally obtained contradictory beliefs through different mental actions in different situations. Because these two contradictory beliefs are in two independent sets of beliefs, Pierre cannot realize the contradictory nature of his beliefs. At this point, Pierre was in a cognitive dissonance situation. Until some other mental actions (such as learning English by indirect means) occur, the products of which (knowledge about translation between English and French) interact and integrate the original two independent sets of beliefs, Pierre finally realized that he himself had contradictory beliefs. This will prompt him to consciously eliminate the contradictory beliefs through some further mental actions.In summary, this article treats Kripke’s puzzle about belief purely as a puzzle about belief attribution. We distinguish between explicitly contradictory beliefs and implicitly contradictory beliefs. By introducing the concept of situation, a normal person can rationally possess implicitly contradictory beliefs due to the unfavorable appearance of empirical facts. The limits of reason should mean that there are no explicitly contradictory beliefs, and that does not conflict with having implicitly contradictory beliefs. A plausible explanation for conflicting beliefs can be given by introducing the concept of mental actions. Returning to the original context in which Kripke’s puzzle about belief was put forward, the analyses and conclusions presented in this paper have the following positive implications: the point of the introduction of mental actions is to take language users into the meaning of that language in a more natural way. Accordingly, a more reasonable theory of meaning should break down the binary relationship between language and the world, include the elements of language users, and fundamentally explore the relationships between language and the world, language and mind, language and social community, and mind and the world.
雒自新. 心智行动视域下的矛盾信念[J]. 浙江大学学报(人文社会科学版), 2023, 53(4): 49-59.
Luo Zixin. Contradictory Beliefs from the Perspective of Mental Action: A New Study of Kripke’s Puzzle about Belief. JOURNAL OF ZHEJIANG UNIVERSITY, 2023, 53(4): 49-59.
1 Lowe E. J., “Does the descriptivist/anti-descriptivist debate have any philosophical significance?” Philosophical Books, Vol. 48, No. 1 (2007), pp. 27-33. 2 Putnam H., “Comments,” in Margalit A. (ed.), Meaning and Use, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1979, pp. 284-288. 3 Chalmers D. J., “The components of content,” in Chalmers D. J. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, pp. 608-633. 4 Searle J., Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983. 5 Nelson M., “Propositional attitude reports,” https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/prop-attitude-reports/, 2022-04-08. 6 Salmon N., “A note on Kripke’s puzzle about belief,” in Berger A. (ed.), Saul Kripke, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011, pp. 235-252. 7 Kripke S. A., “A puzzle about belief,” in Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers, vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. 125-160. 8 Fitch G. W., Saul Kripke, Chesham: Acumen, 2004. 9 Taschek W., “Putting Pierre and Peter in context: on ascribing beliefs,” in Jurtronic-Tihomirovic D. (ed.), The Maribor Papers in Naturalized Semantics, Maribor: Pedago?ka Fakulteta, 1997, pp. 339-343. 10 Santambrogio M., “Belief and translation,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 99, No. 12 (2002), pp. 624-647. 11 Moore J. G., “Misdisquotation and substitutivity: when not to infer belief from assent,” Mind, Vol. 108, No. 430 (1999), pp. 335-366. 12 Burge T., “Two thought experiments revisited,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, Vol. 23, No. 3 (1982), pp. 284-294. 13 Brandom R., Making It Explicit, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994. 14 Marcus R. B., “Rationality and believing the impossible,” in Modalities: Philosophical Essays, New York: Oxford University Press, 1995, pp. 143-161. 15 周龙生: 《CnK的哲学特征初探》,见杜国平编: 《逻辑、智能与哲学》第一辑,北京:社会科学文献出版社,2022年,第146-155页。 16 Erickson G. W. & Fossa J. A., Dictionary of Paradox, Lanham: University Press of America, 1998. 17 ?ukowski P., Paradoxes, Heidelberg: Springer, 2011. 18 Salmon N., “Being of two minds: belief with doubt,” No?s, Vol. 29, No. 1 (1995), pp. 1-20. 19 Priest G., In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent (2nd Edition), New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. 20 Dummett M., Frege: Philosophy of Language, New York: Harper & Row, 1973. 21 Elster J., Logic and Society: Contradictions and Possible Worlds, New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1978. 22 Harman G., Change in View: Principles of Reasoning, Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1986. 23 Dummett M., The Logical Basis of Metaphysics, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991. 24 Kyburg H., Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief, Middletown: Wesleyan University Press, 1961. 25 Makinson D. C., “The paradox of the preface,” Analysis, Vol. 25, No. 6 (1965), pp. 205-207. 26 Sandgren A., “Puzzling Pierre and intentional identity,” Erkenntnis, Vol. 84, No. 4 (2019), pp. 861-875. 27 Kripke S. A., “Outline of a theory of truth,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 72, No. 19 (1975), pp. 690-716. 28 Burge T., “Semantical paradox,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 76, No. 4 (1979), pp. 169-198. 29 Prior A. N., “On a family of paradoxes,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, Vol. 2, No. 1 (1961), pp. 16-32. 30 Burge T., “Epistemic paradox,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 81, No. 1 (1984), pp. 5-29. 31 Richard M., “Kripke’s puzzle about belief,” in Berger A. (ed.), Saul Kripke, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011, pp. 211-234. 32 Burgess J. P., Saul Kripke: Puzzles and Mysteries, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2013. 33 Festinger L., A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1957. 34 Hanna R., “Kant’s theory of judgment,” 2017-10-23, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/kant-judgment/, 2022-04-08. 35 Hampshire S., Thought and Action (New Edition), Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983. 36 张建军等: 《当代逻辑哲学前沿问题研究》,北京:人民出版社,2014年。 37 雒自新、黄华新: 《心智行动及其产品——沃森选择任务新探》,《自然辩证法研究》2012年第12期,第9-13页。