Abstract:Value incommensurability originally meant that different values cannot be placed on the same cardinal scale, and later it was generally referred to as non-conventional comparative relations, including the narrow sense of incommensurability, hard choices, strong value superiority, weak value superiority and pluralism of irreducible value. Hard cases with substantive disputes are related to a broad usage of value incommensurability called hard choices. In order to correctly understand them and provide standardized suggestions for the settlement of corresponding hard cases, it is necessary to further clarify the related concepts of incommensurability, the classification of hard cases and how to respond to hard cases by reasoning.The hardship of hard choices manifests itself in the depletion of reasons as caused by the multi-dimensional comparison of values, for which there are three explanations: semantic indeterminacy, metaphysical indeterminacy and uncertainty. The explanations of indeterminacy deny that there is a uniquely right answer for hard cases. In contrast, the explanation of uncertainty argues the uniquely right answer exists but people may not find it or mistake it due to ignorance. From the point of view of rationality, it is correct to deny it. Because of the existence of substantive disputes, the corresponding hard cases cannot be solved by flipping a coin. Policymakers have to make a choice in recognition of the fact that both options are right.The classification of hard cases with substantive disputes is based on the classification of hard choices, which is related to the pluralism about value properties. The three most important values related to practical reason are moral, prudent and aesthetic. Hard cases mainly involve moral and prudent. Therefore, hard cases can be divided into hard cases caused by prudent conflicts, hard cases caused by moral conflicts and hard cases caused by the incommensurability between moral and prudent. The latter two kinds of cases related to moral value are more important in theory. Hard cases with substantive disputes mainly refer to the hard cases caused by moral conflicts.In dealing with hard cases, case consistency should be taken as the core reasoning method to distinguish the substantive disputes from the superficial disputes and to reveal value conflicts. In the absence of uniform decision-making, policymakers should respect subjectivity and diversity as much as possible. If a uniform decision-making is necessary, the compromise strategy can best guarantee the fairness. If none of the above strategies is suitable, the policymakers must make a biased choice. At this time, some strategies with strong subjectivity or obvious favoritism should not be adopted, instead, there should be some kind of generalized procedural resolution strategy that recognizes the existence of conflicts. For example, in a strategy to avoid future conflicts, even if the choice is biased, it is still reasonable for policymakers to say that they prefer a procedural decision-making strategy to favoring one side over the other. In most cases, the strategy of strengthening one side’s argument and weakening the other side’s argument is unavoidable, but arbitrary strengthening and weakening will lead to the danger of disunity of methods. It seems feasible and necessary to pursue a consistent preference for a procedural approach.
陆幸福, 刘纪伟. 价值不可通约性与理由冲突型疑难案件的应对[J]. 浙江大学学报(人文社会科学版), 2024, 54(10): 97-109.
Lu Xingfu, Liu Jiwei. Value Incommensurability and the Handling of Hard Cases with Substantive Disputes. JOURNAL OF ZHEJIANG UNIVERSITY, 2024, 54(10): 97-109.
1 陈真:《论道德和精明理性的不可通约性》,《求是学刊》2004年第1期,第5-11页。 2 梁上上:《异质利益衡量的公度性难题及其求解——以法律适用为场域展开》,《政法论坛》2014年第4期,第3-19页。 3 王磊:《论法价值的衡量》,见《北大法律评论》编辑委员会(轮值主编:赵英男)主编:《北大法律评论》第18卷第2辑,北京:北京大学出版社,2019年,第173-189页。 4 严崴:《论司法裁判中价值判断的不可通约性》,见陈金钊、谢晖主编:《法律方法》第34卷,北京:研究出版社2021年,第161-174页。 5 Andersson H. & Herlitz A., “Introduction,” in Andersson H. & Herlitz A.(eds.), Value Incommensurability: Ethics, Risk, and Decision-Making, New York: Routledge, 2023, pp. 1-25. 6 Chang R., “Introduction,” in Chang R. (ed.), Incommensurability, Incomparability and Practical Reason, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997, pp. 1-34. 7 英]以赛亚·伯林:《自由论》(修订版),胡传胜译,南京:译林出版社,2011年。 8 Chang R., Making Comparisons Court, New York: Routledge, 2002. 9 Raz J., The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986. 10 Baumann P. & Betzler M., “Introduction,” in Baumann P. & Betzler M. (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. 1-26. 11 Chang R., “Are hard choices cases of incomparability?” Philosophical Issues, Vol. 22, No. 1(2012), pp. 106-126. 12 Dworkin R., Justice for Hedgehogs, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2011. 13 梁慧星:《中国民法典草案建议稿附理由:亲属编》,北京:法律出版社,2013年。 14 Bader R. M., “Kantian axiology and the dualism of practical reason,” in Hirose I. & Olson J. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. 175-202. 15 美]罗纳德·德沃金:《生命的自主权:堕胎、安乐死与个人自由的辩论》,郭贞伶、陈雅汝译,北京:中国政法大学出版社,2013年。 16 Chang R., “Reflections on the reasonable and the rational in conflict resolution,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 83, No. 1 (2009), pp. 133-160. 17 陈林林:《公众意见影响法官决策的理论和实验分析》,《法学研究》2018年第1期,第18-35页。 18 Marino P., Moral Reasoning in Pluralistic World, Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2015. 19 Chang R., “Putting together morality and well-being,” in Baumann P. & Betzler M. (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. 118-158. 20 Hooker B., Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-consequentialist Theory of Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.