Abstract:The world’s first gene-edited baby incident, which happened in Shenzhen, prompted the Chinese legislature to establish a new crime of illegally implanting gene-edited or cloned embryos in the Amendment (Ⅺ) to the Criminal Law of China. However, a clarification on the legal interest of the new crime is in need. In view of the fact that the legislative explanation is quite simple, and no other country in the world has ever had a case, it is difficult to determine its legal interest. This article intends to analyze its legal interest from the perspective of bioethics and clarify the boundary of its punishment.Regarding the nature of the crime, the academic community mainly holds two confrontational viewpoints: the theory of infringing legal interests and the theory of ethical violation. The former believes that the purpose of criminal law is to protect legal interests, while the latter believes that its purpose is to maintain social ethics. Incompatible as the two seem to be, they are two sides of the same coin with different focuses. Behaviors that infringe legal interests inevitably violate social ethics at the same time, and vice versa. The reason why the criminal law can impose penalties on criminal acts is that these acts violate ethical rules at the bottom. Therefore, it is feasible to seek and justify legal interests through ethical norms.In the field of ethics, there is an opposition between deontology and utilitarianism in judging the legitimacy of a behavior. As a medical technology, germline gene editing is value-free, but its application in medical clinics faces doubts about its legitimacy. In this regard, the resort of deontology tends to end up in an inexplicable dilemma, because it is impossible to justify whether there is an absolute order that “the human germline gene should not be edited at any time” or similar abstractions. However, based on utilitarianism, it is not difficult to find that mature germline gene-editing technology can bring positive value to individuals, society, and the country by keeping in line with the “principle of maximizing welfare”, so it is worth promoting its application in medical clinics. Meanwhile, there is a premise that the technology is mature and risk-free.The reason why the legislature prohibits human germline gene editing is that this kind of behavior is seriously harmful at the current immature level of technology. It will not only endanger the life and health of the edited individual but also destroy the order of medical and health management. In the bioethics scholar community, although there is controversy over the legitimacy of germline gene editing, it is an accepted rule not to apply it to clinical treatment, given the current risk and uncertainty. Therefore, the legal interest should be the order of medical and health management. Whereas, the safety of the human gene bank is not the legal interest of this crime. On the one hand, as an abstract and uncertain concept, whether it is a kind of interest worthy of protection is still inconclusive even in the field of ethics. On the other hand, even if it is considered to be an interest worthy of protection, germline gene editing doesn’t compromise this interest as it does nothing to the purity, stability, and diversity of the human gene bank.The order of medical and health management educes that this crime punishes the behavior tendency of “designing babies” through gene editing, rather than the editing of genes for medical experiments. It is necessary to be tolerant of medical experiments, otherwise, the technology will never become mature for clinical application. Of course, such medical experiments should be conducted within a strict and effective regulatory framework which makes this criminal sanction a mere temporary legislation. When the technology becomes mature and risk-free in the future and a consensus is built up to apply it in the fields of treatment and enhancement, etc., this crime will withdraw from the stage of human history. At that time, the post-human society will also undergo earth-shaking changes in terms of compositional structure, family functions, ethical rules, and even the concept of human nature.
叶良芳. 非法植入基因编辑、克隆胚胎罪的保护法益:基于生命伦理的视角[J]. 浙江大学学报(人文社会科学版), 2022, 52(7): 34-48.
Ye Liangfang. On the Legal Interest of Illegally Implanting Gene-Edited or Cloned Embryos: From the Perspective of Bioethics. JOURNAL OF ZHEJIANG UNIVERSITY, 2022, 52(7): 34-48.
张明楷: 《外国刑法纲要》,北京:法律出版社,2020年。2 王海明: 《伦理学导论》,上海:复旦大学出版社,2009年。3 Moore G. E., Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.4 德]米夏埃尔·帕夫利克: 《目的与体系:古典哲学基础上的德国刑法学新思考》,赵书鸿等译,北京:法律出版社,2018年。5 倪正茂、陆庆胜等: 《生命法学引论》,武汉:武汉大学出版社,2005年。6 马永强: 《基因科技犯罪的法益侵害与归责进路》,《法制与社会发展》2021年第4期,第104-121页。7 Anderson W. F., “Human gene therapy: scientific and ethical considerations,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, Vol. 10, No. 3 (1985), pp. 275-291.8 阴建峰、冷枫: 《非法植入基因编辑、克隆胚胎罪之检视与完善》,《扬州大学学报(人文社会科学版)》2021年第3期,第54-65页。9 德]埃里克·希尔根多夫: 《医疗刑法导论》,王芳凯译,北京:北京大学出版社,2021年。10 Moore K. L., Persaud T. & Torchia M. G., The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented Embryology, 10th Edition, Philadelphia: Saunders, 2016.11 Finnis J., Intention and Identity: Collected Essays, volume Ⅱ, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.12 张华夏: 《现代科学与伦理世界:道德哲学的探索与反思》,北京:中国人民大学出版社,2010年。13 英]边沁: 《道德与立法原理导论》,时殷弘译,北京:商务印书馆,2000年。14 Smart J. & Williams B, Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973.15 Melillo T. R., “Gene editing and the rise of designer babies,” Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law, Vol. 50, No. 3 (2017), pp. 757-790.16 黄丁全: 《医疗、法律与生命伦理》,北京:法律出版社,2015年。17 盛豪杰: 《非法植入基因编辑、克隆胚胎罪的解读》,《医学与哲学》2021年第20期,第56-60页。18 王康: 《“基因编辑婴儿”人体试验中的法律责任——基于中国现行法律框架的解释学分析》,《重庆大学学报(社会科学版)》2019年第5期,第134-144页。19 王志祥、安冉: 《涉基因技术行为的刑法规制问题研究——以基因编辑婴儿事件的定性为切入点》,《山东警察学院学报》2020年第2期,第5-12页。20 高铭暄、马克昌主编: 《刑法学》,北京:北京大学出版社、高等教育出版社,2019年。21 赵秉志主编: 《〈刑法修正案(十一)〉理解与适用》,北京:中国人民大学出版社,2021年。22 邱仁宗: 《生命伦理学》(增订版),北京:中国人民大学出版社,2020年。23 Smith K., “Time to start intervening in the human germline? a utilitarian perspective,” Bioethics, Vol. 34, No.1 (2020), pp. 90-104.24 余秋莉: 《论人体生殖系基因编辑行为的刑法应对——兼评贺建奎“基因编辑婴儿”案》,《法律适用》2020年第4期,第22-33页。25 陈晓平: 《试论人类基因编辑的伦理界限》,《自然辩证法通讯》2019年第7期,第1-13页。26 美] 弗朗西斯·福山: 《我们的后人类未来:生物技术革命的后果》,黄立志译,桂林:广西师范大学出版社,2017年。27 Koplin J. J., Gyngell C. & Savulescu J., “Germline gene editing and the precautionary principle,” Bioethics, Vol. 34, No. 1 (2020), pp. 49-59.28 王立铭: 《上帝的手术刀:基因编辑简史》,杭州:浙江人民出版社,2017年。29 马路瑶: 《风险社会视阈下人类胚胎基因编辑的刑事立法立场》,《湖北社会科学》2019年第11期,第153-161页。30 德]阿图尔·考夫曼: 《法律哲学》,刘幸义等译,北京:法律出版社,2004年。31 Gyngell C., Douglas T. & Savulescu J., “The Ethics of Germline Gene Editing,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, Vol. 34, No. 4 (2017), pp. 498-513.32 National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine, Human Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance, Washington D. C.: The National Academies Press, 2017.33 加]弗朗索瓦丝·贝利斯: 《改变遗传:CRISPR与人类基因组编辑的伦理》,陈如译,上海:上海科技教育出版社,2021年。34 刘长秋: 《“基因编辑婴儿事件”的生命法学思考》,《东南法学》2021年第1期,第1-17页。